Category Archives: Fun

Identifying high-order rationality

Identifying high-order rationality is a forthcoming paper in Econometrica from my favourite behavioural game theorist, Terri Kneeland. For those of you who are not familiar with the inside baseball, Econometrica is one of the top two journals in economics and good economists can go their entire careers without publishing a paper in Econometrica. Getting your first paper published in Econometrica, as Kneeland has, is a pretty awesome achievement.

So what makes Kneeland’s paper so good? Well, it is a simple (yet novel) idea that was implemented in a very clean fashion.[1] Economic models of strategic interactions rely on the notion of rationality, where an agent is defined to be rational if they make optimal decisions given their available information.[3] This definition is actually rather weak and, as Kneeland demonstrates, most people satisfy rationality in simple environments. In some cases, however, economic models require a much stricter notion known as common knowledge of rationality. An agent is called first-order rational if they are rational. They are second-order rational if they are first-order rational and they believe that others are first-order rational. They are third-order rational if they are second-order rational and believe that others are also second-order rational. Common knowledge of rationality is the state where all agents are infinite-order rational.

The innovation in Kneeland’s paper is that she implemented a new experimental design that, with minimal assumptions, can identify a subject’s order of rationality. The process that Kneeland developed is as follows. Suppose that you are standing in a circle with a large number of other people. Everyone in the circle must choose a between A, B and C. You will receive an amount of money that depends on your choice and the choice of the person standing to your left. You are given a table outlining how much money you will receive in each situation. Consider the following table as an example. In this example, you will choose a row, the person to your left will choose a column, and you will receive the amount shown in the corresponding box. Which option would you choose?

A B C
A 12 16 14
B 8 12 10
C 6 10 8

You might have noticed that the option A will give you your best outcome, irrespective of what the person to your left chooses. An economist would call option A a dominant strategy. A first-order rational person will always choose their dominant strategy, if they have one.

 

Next, consider the following table. (Again, you choose a row, and the person to your left chooses a column).

 

A B C
A 20 14 8
B 16 2 18
C 0 16 16

In this case your choice is harder, because there are no dominant strategies for you. If you think that the person to your left will choose A then you should also choose A. But if you think the person to your left will choose C then you should choose B. How should you decide what to do?

In Kneeland’s experiment, you could also see the payoff tables for everyone else in the circle. So to decide what you should do, you should probably look at the payoff table for the person standing to your left. If they have a dominant strategy, then perhaps you think they will choose their dominant strategy and you may then respond accordingly. If you were to behave in this fashion then you would be displaying second-order rationality.

In other, more complicated, situations perhaps the person to your left doesn’t have a dominant strategy either but the person to their left does (that is, they person two spots to your left has a dominant strategy). Perhaps you think that the person to your left will notice that the person to their left has a dominant strategy, and that you could use this to predict the behaviour of the person directly to your left. Then, you can make your choice taking all of this information into account. If you do this then you are third-order rational.

This logical reasoning process can be traced back further to identify people of even higher orders of rationality[2]. This special circular structure (called a ring game) is exactly what Kneeland used to identify the order of rationality of her experimental subjects.

So what were the results? Kneeland finds that 93 of her subjects are first-order rational, 71 percent are second-order rational, 44 percent are third-order rational and only 22 percent are fourth-order rational. Kneeland is very cautious about over-interpreting her results, but in a blog post I need not be so careful. The results indicate, to me, that the standard assumption of rationality is not too far off being correct in simple environments.  However, the results also indicate that at most 22 percent of subjects could possibly satisfy the common knowledge of rationality assumption even in a relatively simple environment, indicating that common knowledge of rationality is not the most realistic of assumptions in many environments.

 

 


 

[1] Econometrica tends to publish two types of papers. The first is simple and clean papers that are good fun to read. The second is technically complicated, but brilliant, papers that can take days or weeks for experts to understand, and are pretty much incomprehensible to everyone else.

[2] An interesting question is to ask how you should reason when no one in the circle has a dominant strategy. The standard (but not entirely uncontroversial) recommendation would be that you should choose a Nash equilibrium strategy, named after John Nash who was played by Russel Crowe in the movie A Beautiful Mind.

[3] Note that this definition of rationality doesn’t mention anything about selfishness, nor make any assumptions about preferences, nor include any other of the crazy stuff that the anti-economics crowd seem to think economists mean by the word “rational”. At the most basic level you are rational if you make “good” decisions, given your information at the time of the decision, for whatever your personal evaluation of “good” is.

Papers with great names

Apologies for the lack of posting lately. I have a couple of papers that I am planning to cover here shortly, including one by my favourite up-and-coming behavioural theorist (I’m just waiting for the final version of that paper to be made publicly available).

But, for now, we have an entry into the “Best paper title of 2015” competition:

Are we all overconfident in the long run? Evidence from one million marathon participants.

There is just so much going on in there. From the obviously hilarious pun, to the less obvious reference to this classic paper, it’s all happening. Well done Prof. Krawczyk and Prof. Wilamowski.

Advent Calendar of beer part 3

Now, for the final 8 beers in the advent calendar of beers.

Beer #17: Parallel 49 Sahti Claws Finnish Sahti 7.7% ABV 35 IBU
Rated: 4 out of 10
I had never heard of  sahti before, so I looked it up on wikipedia. A sahti is made with juniper berries, and apparently often has a banana flavour that is caused by isopental acetate (which, if memory serves, is a favourite ester of high school science teachers as it smells strongly of bananas). I am not a fan of gin, so I was a little apprehensive of the juniper berries. This beer is certainly not for me. I did hunker down and finish it, and it had grown on me a little by the end but I would certainly not have another.

Beer #18: Red Racer Imperial IPA 9% ABV 90 IBU
Rated: 5 out of 10
I took yesterday off, so there’s two beers for tonight. This is a super strong, super bitter IPA. But it just seems a bit one dimensional. The flavours seem to meld into a single bittery taste, with a side of sweetness, and I can’t get the distinct fruity and bitter tastes that you would expect from a good IPA. On the plus side, it pours with a nice coppery colour.

Click through to see the rest of the beer reviews.

Continue reading

Advent calendar of beer part 2

To keep the posts from getting too long, I am going to split my reviews of the advent calendar of beer into 3 parts. Given that we are up to the 9th beer, it is time to start part 2.

Beer #9: Parallel 49 Hoparazzi Lager 6.0% ABV 43 IBU
Rated: 7 out of 10
This beer combines the hoppiness of a west coast IPA with a lager. One of the consequences of this is that the beer has a vaguely unpleasant nose. It has a nice rich golden colour, but doesn’t hold it’s head very well. The bitterness, although not slight at 43 IBUs, is not overpowering and you still get some nice floral tones and an underlying crispness. It’s a decent beer, but I’m jut not sure when I would drink it. If I want a hoppy beer, I would prefer to go the full hog and have an IPA (like beer #3, the Filthy Dirty IPA), and if I want a lager I would prefer something a bit crisper.

Beer #10: Red Race Extra Special Bitter 5.6% ABV
Rated: 7 out of 10
The initial indications on this beer were all positive. It has a nice nose, and pours with a nice head. On the other hand, the taste profile is somewhat lacking. It has the bitterness profile that you would expect from an English style bitter beer, but the finish feels like it is missing a tone or two. It’s not a bad attempt at an ESB, and the fact that it can pour a nice head is a refreshing change, but it’s not quite there either.

 

Continue reading

Advent Calendar of beer

If there is one thing I have learnt from PJ Healy, it is that a good experimental economist needs to take his or her beer drinking very seriously.

Kiri bought me a beer advent calendar for the celebratory season with 24 different beers, half from the Parallel 49 brewery and half from the Central City Brewers (who make the red racer beers). I figure this provides a good opportunity to follow PJ’s lead and start reviewing some beers. I’ll keep updating this post throughout the month as I enjoy the beers.

Beer #1: Parallel 49 Schwarzwald 9% ABV 22 IBU
Rated: 5 out of 10
This beer is an interesting one. It is flavoured with chocolate and cherries, in the style of black forest cake. I normally really, really dislike flavoured beers, but this one is almost passable. The flavouring is achieved using cacao nibs and sweet dark cherries. The colour is very dark, almost black with a hint of red, and there is almost no head. The alcohol content is probably a bit too high, as it seems to overpower some of the other flavours. The chocolate and cherry flavours are not too overpowering, but not really subtle either. Not bad for a flavoured beer, but not great for a beer.

Beer #2: Red Racer Pilsner 5% ABV
Rated: 7 out of 10
Like all Pilsners this beer is very inoffensive. It is crisp and clean like a Pilsner should be, but the finish is just a little bit on the creamy side compared to what I would expect from a great Pils. It is a very pale yellow, again with very little head (I think this will be trend throughout the entire case). A good beer, that you could just keep on drinking on a hot summer’s day. I almost gave this one an 8, but knocked an extra point for the non-PIlsnery aftertaste.

Click beneath the fold to read the rest of the beer reviews…

Continue reading

World Cup betting pool: the outcomes

I have had a request to follow up on my previous post on the World Cup betting pool that I ran in my department. Specifically, I was asked to address whether the betting satisfied the four desiderata that I outlined in the previous post.

For a brief refresher, I used a model where we treat each of the teams (or a group of teams) in the World Cup as a room in a share house, and each of the participants in the betting pool as a tenant in the house. Then the goal is to match rooms to tenants, and allocate shares of the rent across tenants, so that:

  • the outcome should be efficient
  • no one should envy anyone else’s room/rent combination
  • the sum of the rents should be equal to the total rent payable for the house
  • the mechanism should be incentive compatible (i.e. no one should be able to manipulate the outcome by lying about their preferences)

So, did my betting pool satisfy these four criteria? The short answer is that it is impossible to guarantee all four at once.

The longer answer is that, in summary, if we can assume that no one lied about their preferences, then the other three conditions are automatically satisfied. If we think this assumption might be violated, then the first three conditions will still be satisfied if people have misrepresented their preferences in an optimal fashion. If we think that people might have misrepresented their preferences sub-optimally, then condition three will still be satisfied, but there is nothing that we can say about the first two conditions.

For more details, read on!

Continue reading

Cheap talk can be valuable

I was a huge fan of the blog Cheap Talk. I say was only because the posting rate there has trickled down to almost nothing (sure, you could say the same thing about this blog, but I also have practically no readers). But, occasionally they still put up a new post that, more often than not, includes terrific passages such as this one:

So, is Hachette, a French company, confused because in France they put price on the x-axis and quantity on the y-axis so marginal revenue is upside down? Surely Jean Tirole can sort that out for you.

 

An economist’s betting pool

I am running a betting pool amongst some members of the department for the upcoming World Cup. Now, I suppose that the normal thing to do would be to assign teams randomly amongst the participants sweepstakes style. But for an economist, this seems like a rather inefficient thing to do. What if one person really wants Brazil but draws Germany, and someone else really wants Germany but draws Brazil?

Fortunately, there is an entire literature on what is known as the “rental harmony problem.” In the rental harmony problem, there are a group of house mates who are renting a new house and they wish to work out who should have each room and what share of the rent each should pay. We want the outcome to satisfy a few properties:

  • the outcome should be efficient
  • no one should envy anyone else’s room/rent combination
  • the sum of the rents should be equal to the total rent payable for the house
  • the mechanism should be incentive compatible (i.e. no one should be manipulate the outcome by lying about their preferences)

Unfortunately, it is impossible to satisfy all four of these conditions at once (this can be demonstrated as an application of the Vickrey-Clarke-Groves mechanism; if we enforce strict budget balance no mechanism can be found). Therefore, we must relax one of the conditions, and the usual thing to do is to relax the last condition.

At this point, mathematicians and economists differ in their approach. Mathematicians tend to simply assume that people will tell the truth; this is the approach taken in this extremely elegant paper by Su [1]. Economists, on the other hand, tend to assume that people will lie if it is profitable, and attempt to minimize the damage caused by the lying; this is the approach taken in this paper by Abdulkadiroglu, Sonmez and Unver.

Therefore, for my World Cup betting pool I will be using the mechanism described in the Abdulkadiroglu et al paper. Each team (or group of teams) will be treated as a room in the house, and the total prize money available will be treated as the total rent for the house. Each participant will need to submit a vector of bids (one bid for each team or group of teams), and the algorithm will allocate teams and entry costs to the participants. In a follow up post I will outline the bids that were submitted and the outcome of the algorithm.

 

Additional notes for economists:

Continue reading

SMBC comics

Zach Weiner over at SMBC comics often writes economics related comics. Now, I know that most economists don’t really like his comics because he often gets the details wrong and regularly presents economics in a fairly negative light. But I am willing to look past these flaws because the comics are usually still pretty funny.

Take this one for example. [Note: I’m happy to hear ideas on better ways to embed the comics onto this site. I’m new to this stuff, so not really sure the best way to do it.]

I mean, yeah, the elicitation mechanism isn’t incentive compatible and of course the guy actually does want to buy beans at non-equilibrium prices (I’d buy everything at the non-equilibrium price of zero if I could), but it’s funny.

And if you want to know what my board game nights are like…

Update: Only a few days after I put this post up Zach posted this comic up. Horrible misapplication of the EMH. The comic could be partially saved if the text was edited to read “Sorry. But, according to the EMH, if sex with you were a good idea, somebody would be doing it already.”